Sunday, January 13, 2013

Having your cake and eating it too; How the fight for autonomous lives leads to fighting against poverty


In this paper, I will argue that the importance of a life’s autonomy is enough moral obligation to give the excesses of people who are already living autonomous lives so that others may have a more fulfilling life. I will show that the need for an autonomous life is such that moral obligation to donate through aid agencies will supersede the wanting of things not as important as granting a person an autonomous life.

Before I begin, I must clarify the true aims of this paper. I will be focusing on the autonomy and the quality of that autonomy that all human lives share. For this paper, we will assume that in order to have a good life, one must be autonomous in the fullest extent in whatever situation, place, or state he or she resides in. We will also assume that the definition for autonomy is one that applies to how much real choice a person has to go about living his or her life in a certain locale based on the amount or access to certain goods, services, and social functions he or she has. For there to be complete autonomy, a person must fulfill the criteria [1] for all those necessary components needed to lead a normal life in relation to their place of residence. For instance, an autonomous life should be free to not only choose trivial things like food sources or perhaps even consumer goods, but also allow for some flexibility in the enrichment of one’s life. Whether it is by fulfilling a certain goal or by adopting a lifestyle that requires a unique combination of required goods and/or a specialized belief system (i.e. vegetarianism, religious beliefs etc.), one must be able to wholesomely convey these senses of autonomy. In order for that to happen, one must be in a community that has the means to support the enrichment of all people's lives and generally support their autonomy. That being said, there must be suitable conditions that in no way take away from the autonomy of people before someone is said to be living a complete life.
Taking all things into account, we can move on to understanding how poverty negatively affects autonomy. More importantly, we need to identify how lack of funds at the micro level severely limits the fulfillment of both “societal” and “stand alone” criteria of autonomy. Let's take education as a preliminary example. Education is an important aspect to a person's autonomy because of the essential building blocks it provides to further enrich a person's life. Education works to not only broaden the options of work for a person, it also expands their possible aspirations, effectively adding autonomy. Yet education is dependent on societal functions; without certain institutions and human interactions, education would be a useless requirement for autonomy unlike perhaps basic needs which stand alone as a sector of autonomy. The simple distinction of how these provisions relate to autonomy is what is important here; there are some provisions which support autonomy based on societal functions, and others that can stand alone to preserve physical life. Although those that stand by themselves may seem more important, both types are crucial to the development of autonomous lives. Applied to real world problems, the cost of education serves as its biggest threat. While many believe that education should be free (and some speculate a right as well), we know this to not be true about many poor countries. Many poor African countries in fact do not spend more than 3% of their GDP for education across primary, secondary, and tertiary schools (Guardian) and some don’t even fund education at all, while the United States invests 5.7% of its GDP (NationMaster).
This lack of support of education is in that sense a denial of education to a section of the world that could very well do with increased levels of education for all children regardless of grade level. Because spending on education is so low, it is expected that education to many families is not a given but instead a difficult choice, and in many cases another sacrifice made to simply survive. The levels of education needed to achieve autonomy then, as stated above, is not being met in countries with severe poverty. Consequentially, we can make a distinction that lack of certain goods or services does not describe poverty, but rather that poverty causes these lapses in suitable conditions, and the loss of autonomy.

Taking the importance of the positive relationship between autonomy and living a good life into consideration, we have proven that poverty has a profound effect on the quality of autonomy and therefore the quality of life of a person. We must however be cognizant of the fact that a simple demonstration like a lack of education is normally not the only factor which leads to a lessening of the quality of autonomy and one's life; even “stand alone” provisions suffer because of poverty. It seems to stand to reason then that we may feel some sort of obligation to cure poverty so that unsuitable conditions affecting autonomy disappear altogether. Yet poverty in itself is not a reason to feel morally obligated to give any aid. Thinking that simply curing poverty for the sake of increasing personal wealth is a moral obligation is a flawed argument if we develop the idea of moral obligation.
 A moral obligation is a response to an internal judgment brought about by what many would take to be a conscience in relation to an outside stimulus. How that "conscience" is developed or what develops it can be debated, but the important aspect is that moral obligations come about when there is an absolute external stimuli to which someone takes it upon him or herself to settle.  We take poverty to imply an extreme lack of funds, but we have no means to figure out at what limit one becomes impoverished. It is very difficult if not impossible to pinpoint a global poverty line. Many institutions try to strike an arbitrary line, which can help in understanding the plight of very extreme poverty cases, but it still does not answer the practical question. It seems foolish to imply that someone who is one cent above the poverty line has full autonomy whilst the person one cent below does not. Therefore, poverty must be dealt with in relative terms, not absolute terms. The conflict of autonomy on the other hand must be dealt with in absolute terms. One cannot simply have partial autonomy; there either is autonomy, or there is not autonomy. Relating the problem of autonomy and the problem of poverty then, moral obligations can only arise in problems of autonomy (absolutist) and not poverty (relativist). That is why there is only a moral obligation to ensure a full and autonomous life and not to ensure private financial security.
 This can be shown with the easy rescue case [2]. The point of the obligation in the example is not to ensure that the drowning victim be in possession of a flotation device. It is instead to ensure that the drowning victim does not end up drowning. There is a moral obligation to protect life in general, not private holdings in general. The pond example can continue to stretch our thinking as to how much one should really invest into fulfilling their personal moral obligation to ensure autonomy amongst other people. Clearly, before trying to do so, one must ensure that his or her autonomy is not put in danger. Sacrificing one's chance at an education to provide an education for another seems like the lifeguard exchanging places with the drowning victim. That somewhat defeats the purpose of embracing universal autonomy if at the end of the day there is still someone who drowns. Yet we cannot simply stand idly and try to calculate exactly how much energy and time will be sacrificed by the person tossing the life preserver in. By the time those calculations are through, the life preserver has become rather useless. Instead, we can make a simple judgment to toss the life preserver into the water because it is of no use to us, because we are not in a position of needing it. That is the key to understanding exactly where the line must be drawn.
If autonomy is to be described as the fulfilling of criteria concerning the quality of life of a person, we can imagine different categories being filled to reach a certain acceptable level. Whatever those levels may be will differ from community to community, but the concept is universal. There must be a pre-decided minimum level for each criterion that allows for any member in the community to become completely autonomous and able to enrich his or her life. Anything over those levels that grant autonomy can be seen as excess; excess that can be better used if invested in giving autonomy to those who lack the minimum basics for being autonomous. This is not to be interpreted as a redistribution endeavor. This rule simply implies that any excess of goods, funds, or social capital be not allowed to waste after a person's autonomy has been completely satisfied. There is indeed a moral obligation to not allow those things to go to waste, and rather to allow them to improve the life of someone who has diminished chances at autonomy. An example will illustrate this process. Say you are at a restaurant eating a nice dinner. You are more than wealthy enough to afford the meal, as well as the valet service outside. You go out to dinner to celebrate a birthday or an anniversary, both of which are goals or aspirations whose completion is as much of a reflection of past ability and effort as it is about personal "on the moment" enjoyment and pleasure. Once the meal is done, food scraps remain on the plate that you decide was just too big of a portion for you or anyone else at the table to handle. You therefore reject to go on any further with that meal and allow the waiter who you will tip handsomely to take the plate away from you.
Those food scraps now have two possible places to go. The landfill, where they will sit for months idly rotting away into nothing, or the coal burning plant which has been retrofitted to process food scraps as sources of energy. Clearly, the more efficient choice is to send the food scraps off to the plant where the excess food will be used to its fullest extent rather than wasting away. That is the same principle behind what level of obligation people with more than autonomous lives have to give. I'm not implying we should give out food scraps to those less fortunate than us. I am implying however that at the end of the day, people who live fully autonomous lives have gathered a certain excess of goods in many categories, an excess that we are morally obligated to donate. In some if not most cases, there is much more than "food scraps" in terms of quantity of excess in many wealthy nations. If we visit Singer's efforts, we can see that a small donation can really go a long way towards helping someone gain autonomy (Singer 90-93) in a place where the standards to achieve it are not as high as wealthier states or communities. So the argument stands clear; if one is already living an autonomous life as described by the fulfillment of criteria regarding autonomy in a community, then whatever excess is to be had in each of those criteria should be donated to those who still struggle to gain autonomy. Aid agencies will help help distribute the excess in a way where the “ratio effect” will work the best, so the donations must go there.

What happens however when someone does not have any excesses? Do they now no longer have an obligation to give? Perhaps those that barely cover the necessary autonomy and struggle to maintain it could be forgiven for not feeling the same moral obligation to help out someone else. Yet there could be people who are very well off but still feel that certain lacking aspirations need to be fulfilled before they are completely autonomous, and will therefore never be obligated to give. This makes a system so that those who are very well off and can generate copious amounts of different aspirations will continue to do so instead of generating excess to give to those in need. Essentially, one might end up paying for an infatuation with tennis rather than saving someone's life which sounds very bizarre if not downright wrong.

There are two approaches to resolving this problem. The first is the time constraint approach. If someone is so wealthy to keep continuously generating new things, they will inevitably continue to do so, only until there is a crucial time constraint. We can assume that most of the people who would be able to do this have a job that allows for them to pay for such things, but also takes away crucial time to do them in. For cases of inheritance, the lack of a job may give more hours to do things in, but not so many that would give the person a chance to circumvent there only being 24 hours in a day. In that case, there would still be considerable excess to be donated as a person may only be constrained to a handful of truly wanted aspirations which could be seen as legitimate if they stood alone.
The second approach deals with the fact of evaluating a situation dealing with no excess at all for someone who is not extremely wealthy but rather well off and technically autonomous, yet still oddly not morally obligated to give to someone who really is in need. This may require a reworking of the understanding of autonomy in order to settle the matter of aspirations. Instead of dealing with the previous definition of autonomy as including aspirations, we could have the fulfillment of autonomy include only the basic necessities of life within a community [3] and have aspirations stand alone as an optional sector. The basic necessities of life would also have to be placed in a range of acceptable values for each sector so as to determine what is absolutely needed to be autonomous and which is over-indulgence or excess. To obtain autonomy, those sectors must be fully filled and be in a stable condition. Any excess in those categories still has a moral obligation to be donated to those who still strive to achieve autonomy. In that case, aspirations become secondary values that can only be fully endorsed once autonomy has been reached, giving a greater need to fulfill the needs of autonomy for people who don’t have it as of yet. To ensure that aspirations do not become too superfluous however, a standing limit must be met as to how much people are morally obligated to donate. For this value, we can take a simple formula. People should be morally obligated to donate the same percentage of their yearly costs of maintaining aspirations to people who are still seeking autonomy, but only up to 15%. In numerical terms, if Jones is looking to spend 5% of his $60,000 yearly salary on tennis lessons ($3000), he should be prepared to spend an additional $3000 on donations.
This order may sound arbitrary, but it has its own purpose behind it. These donations only go to people who are still struggling to establish autonomy, let alone their own aspirations. Normally, these people were born, without their consent obviously, in places where the propensity to become autonomous is much lower than in other places. This is a fact often overlooked when deciding on the merits of donating and whether or not "fate" simply wanted there to be people who struggle and people who do well; donating the equivalent amount of what one would spend on his or her own aspirations forces one to look at the disparity between even having no excess and living an autonomous life apparently on the edge of not being autonomous and realizing the true cost of tennis lessons or other aspirations. I cannot simply stay here and say that aspirations are not important, but in relation to other people's plights, they do start to dwarf in importance. The 15% limit also is in no way purely arbitrary. There are people whose lives are definitely shaped by their aspirations (professional athletes for example), and asking for them to match their investment on that level seems too demanding and could possibly relieve them of their autonomy, if not permanently momentarily. The 15% also ensures that a sizable amount is donated (taking Singer's ratio example, 15% of Kobe Bryant's investment in being a great basketball player would give eyesight to many people), but this exact value can be evaluated and perhaps more precisely defined with further research about the effects 15% would have on people who truly take aspirations to describe their lives.
The main goal of this provision however is that people should be morally obligated to understand the worth of what they may take for granted put against the very real problem of lack of autonomy in people’s lives. By showing the disparity in autonomy and not funds, I have proven that a moral obligation lies in truly valuing what some take for granted or take for useless, without having to sacrifice autonomy, in hopes of helping gain autonomy to those that do not have it.

Footnotes

1.      These sectors include things such as basic needs (shelter, food, water etc.), aspirations, education, healthcare, social constructs, government aid, and cultural enrichment. In order for people to have complete autonomy, they must fulfill these criteria to their fullest extent by either investing in them (education) or paying for them up front (food and water).
2.      The easy rescue case refers to the drowning victim needing you to toss the life preserver in the water at no cost to you. Because it is so easy, you are morally obligated to go ahead and toss the life preserver in the water.
3.      The new requirements of autonomy no longer require the aspiration sector to be fully met; yet all previously mentioned sectors still need to be met.


Works Cited

NationMaster. "Education spending (% of GDP) (most recent) by country ." January 2000-2002. NationMaster Website. May 2011 <http://www.nationmaster.com/graph/edu_edu_spe-education-spending-of-gdp>.

Singer, Peter. The Life You Can Save. New York: Random House, 2010.

UNESCO. "African Education Spending." 2011. The Guardian Website. May 2011 <https://spreadsheets.google.com/ccc?key=0AonYZs4MzlZbdEVSNzJYd29Da2c0YjFtbmE4aWh0akE&hl=en#gid=0>.

No comments: